WHAT IS A PHILOSOPHER?
By SIMON CRITCHLEY
There are as many definitions of philosophy as there are philosophers
– perhaps there are even more. After three millennia of philosophical
activity and disagreement, it is unlikely that we’ll reach consensus,
and I certainly don’t want to add more hot air to the volcanic cloud of
unknowing. What I’d like to do in the opening column in this new venture
— The Stone — is to kick things off by asking a slightly different
question: what is a philosopher?
As Alfred North Whitehead said, philosophy is a series of footnotes
to Plato. Let me risk adding a footnote by looking at Plato’s
provocative definition of the philosopher that appears in the middle of
his dialogue, “Theaetetus,” in a passage that some scholars consider a
“digression.” But far from being a footnote to a digression, I think
this moment in Plato tells us something hugely important about what a
philosopher is and what philosophy does.
Socrates tells the story of Thales, who was by some accounts the
first philosopher. He was looking so intently at the stars that he fell
into a well. Some witty Thracian servant girl is said to have made a
joke at Thales’ expense — that in his eagerness to know what went on in
the sky he was unaware of the things in front of him and at his feet.
Socrates adds, in Seth Benardete’s translation, “The same jest suffices
for all those who engage in philosophy.”
What is a philosopher, then? The answer
is clear: a laughing stock, an absent-minded buffoon, the butt of
countless jokes from Aristophanes’ “The Clouds” to Mel Brooks’s “History
of the World, part one.” Whenever the philosopher is compelled to talk
about the things at his feet, he gives not only the Thracian girl but
the rest of the crowd a belly laugh. The philosopher’s clumsiness in
worldly affairs makes him appear stupid or, “gives the impression of
plain silliness.” We are left with a rather Monty Pythonesque definition
of the philosopher: the one who is silly.
But as always with Plato, things are not necessarily as they first
appear, and Socrates is the greatest of ironists. First, we should
recall that Thales believed that water was the universal substance out
of which all things were composed. Water was Thales’ philosophers’
stone, as it were. Therefore, by falling into a well, he inadvertently
presses his basic philosophical claim.
But there is a deeper and more troubling layer of irony here that I
would like to peel off more slowly. Socrates introduces the “digression”
by making a distinction between the philosopher and the lawyer, or what
Benardete nicely renders as the “pettifogger.” The lawyer is compelled
to present a case in court and time is of the essence. In Greek legal
proceedings, a strictly limited amount of time was allotted for the
presentation of cases. Time was measured with a water clock or clepsydra, which literally steals time, as in the Greek kleptes,
a thief or embezzler. The pettifogger, the jury, and by implication the
whole society, live with the constant pressure of time. The water of
time’s flow is constantly threatening to drown them.
The freedom of the philosopher consists in either moving freely from topic to topic or simply spending years returning to the same topic out of perplexity, fascination and curiosity.
By contrast, we might say, the philosopher is the person who has time
or who takes time. Theodorus, Socrates’ interlocutor, introduces the
“digression” with the words, “Aren’t we at leisure, Socrates?” The
latter’s response is interesting. He says, “It appears we are.” As we
know, in philosophy appearances can be deceptive. But the basic contrast
here is that between the lawyer, who has no time, or for whom time is
money, and the philosopher, who takes time. The freedom of the
philosopher consists in either moving freely from topic to topic or
simply spending years returning to the same topic out of perplexity,
fascination and curiosity.
Pushing this a little further, we might say that to philosophize is
to take your time, even when you have no time, when time is constantly
pressing at your back. The busy readers of The New York Times will
doubtless understand this sentiment. It is our hope that some of them
will make the time to read The Stone. As Wittgenstein says, “This is how
philosophers should salute each other: ‘Take your time.’ ” Indeed, it
might tell you something about the nature of philosophical dialogue to
confess that my attention was recently drawn to this passage from
Theaetetus in leisurely discussions with a doctoral student at the New
School, Charles Snyder.
Socrates says that those in the constant press of business, like
lawyers, policy-makers, mortgage brokers and hedge fund managers, become
”bent and stunted” and they are compelled “to do crooked things.” The
pettifogger is undoubtedly successful, wealthy and extraordinarily
honey-tongued, but, Socrates adds, “small in his soul and shrewd and a
shyster.” The philosopher, by contrast, is free by virtue of his or her otherworldliness, by their capacity to fall into wells and appear silly.
Socrates adds that the philosopher neither sees nor hears the
so-called unwritten laws of the city, that is, the mores and conventions
that govern public life. The philosopher shows no respect for rank and
inherited privilege and is unaware of anyone’s high or low birth. It
also does not occur to the philosopher to join a political club or a
private party. As Socrates concludes, the philosopher’s body alone
dwells within the city’s walls. In thought, they are elsewhere.
This all sounds dreamy, but it isn’t. Philosophy should come with the
kind of health warning one finds on packs of European cigarettes:
PHILOSOPHY KILLS. Here we approach the deep irony of Plato’s words.
Plato’s dialogues were written after Socrates’ death. Socrates was
charged with impiety towards the gods of the city and with corrupting
the youth of Athens. He was obliged to speak in court in defense of
these charges, to speak against the water-clock, that thief of time. He
ran out of time and suffered the consequences: he was condemned to death
and forced to take his own life.
A couple of generations later, during the uprisings against
Macedonian rule that followed the death of Alexander the Great in 323
B.C.E., Alexander’s former tutor, Aristotle, escaped Athens saying, “I
will not allow the Athenians to sin twice against philosophy.” From the
ancient Greeks to Giordano Bruno, Spinoza, Hume and right up to the
shameful lawsuit that prevented Bertrand Russell from teaching at the
City College of New York in 1940 on the charge of sexual immorality and
atheism, philosophy has repeatedly and persistently been identified with
blasphemy against the gods, whichever gods they might be. Nothing is
more common in the history of philosophy than the accusation of impiety.
Because of their laughable otherworldliness and lack of respect for
social convention, rank and privilege, philosophers refuse to honor the
old gods and this makes them politically suspicious, even dangerous.
Might such dismal things still happen in our happily enlightened age?
That depends where one casts one’s eyes and how closely one looks.
Perhaps the last laugh is with the philosopher. Although the
philosopher will always look ridiculous in the eyes of pettifoggers and
those obsessed with maintaining the status quo, the opposite happens
when the non-philosopher is obliged to give an account of justice in
itself or happiness and misery in general. Far from eloquent, Socrates
insists, the pettifogger is “perplexed and stutters.”
Of course, one might object, that ridiculing someone’s stammer isn’t a
very nice thing to do. Benardete rightly points out that Socrates
assigns every kind of virtue to the philosopher apart from moderation.
Nurtured in freedom and taking their time, there is something dreadfully
uncanny about the philosopher, something either monstrous or god-like
or indeed both at once. This is why many sensible people continue to
think the Athenians had a point in condemning Socrates to death. I leave
it for you to decide. I couldn’t possibly judge.
Simon Critchley is chair of philosophy at the New School for
Social Research in New York, and part-time professor at Tilburg
University in the Netherlands. He is the author of several books,
including “The Book of Dead Philosophers,” and is moderator of this
series.